International Human Rights: Torture versus Ill-Treatment
Why does international human rights law distinguish between the
concepts of ‘torture’ and ‘ill-treatment’? Do you consider this distinction
well-founded?
The distinction between torture and ill-treatment is not well-founded
because there is no functional framework defining the purposes of these two
differentiated concepts. To rectify this lack of clarity, torture and
ill-treatment should be understood as completely distinct tools that address
separate issues. Cleaving the two ideas apart and setting them against
different social ills not only creates a clearer distinction that simplifies
the legal regime addressing coercive state action (torture), but it also
develops a more comprehensive human rights framework that can now use one of
its foundational concepts (ill-treatment) to address systemic failures.
International human rights distinguishes between torture and
ill-treatment. The distinction exists throughout human rights legal documents,
starting with the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR). Article 5 says
that, “No person shall be subjected to torture or to cruel, inhuman or
degrading treatment or punishment.” Cruel, inhuman, or degrading treatment is
similar to the concept of ill-treatment in other international human rights
documents, such as the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR).
Wording distinctions should be given meaningful legal difference. Torture
is defined in the Convention Against Torture (CAT) as (1) the infliction of “severe
pain or suffering,” (2) “intentionally,” (3) “for [specific] purposes,” (4) by “a
public official or other person acting in an official capacity.” Definitions of
torture differ in other international human rights treaties but, for our
purposes, this definition captures the essence of torture’s legal components. Ill-treatment
may be distinguished along three dimensions. First, by a lower level of pain or
suffering. Second, lacking intentionality or purposiveness. Third, a person
acting in their private capacity, or in an unofficial capacity.
Ill-treatment has been defined by bounded thresholds of physical and
mental suffering. The European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) thinks that, “ill-treatment
must attain a minimum level of severity if it is to fall within [ECHR] Article
3. Assessment of this minimum is relative: depends on all the circumstances of
the case, such as the nature and context of the treatment, its duration, [and] its
physical or mental effects.” A v UK (1998). On the other end of the spectrum,
the CAT’s Article 16 defines ill-treatment relative to torture; as acts that
are similar, but do not amount, to torture. The Human Rights Committee (HRC) has
similarly identified the “severity” of ill-treatment as a distinguishing
factor, along with its “nature [and] purpose.” Along this dimension,
ill-treatment amounts to some minimum level of suffering but not too much
suffering.
Ill-treatment has also been distinguished based on the intentions of
the defendants. The ECtHR in Gafgen v Germany (2010) emphasized the purposive
elements of torture, which are not necessary for ill-treatment. The distinction
is an important broadening of the scope of what is captured by ill-treatment. Perpetrators
actions may be purposive, such as torturing a victim to get information, but
not intentional towards someone suffering severe mental anguish, such as the
torture victim’s mother. Stripping away intentionality as a legal element also
opens the door to broader conceptions of ill-treatment, such as social torture,
which can be seen in American ghettos that “systemically reproduc[e] its
deepest pattern of social exclusion, inter-racial hostility, and interpersonal
violence.” Social Torture: The Case of Northern Uganda. To fully incorporate a
concept as broad as social torture, ill-treatment must also be distinguished along
a third dimension: private versus public actors.
The prohibition against torture is targeted towards public officials
and those acting in an official capacity. This requirement is sensible in the
modern human rights paradigm that focuses on controlling state action. Thus, in
that dynamic, the prohibition on torture operates erga omnes (an obligation
that a state owes to everyone) to prohibit states and state institutions from
torturing. However, the obligation is broad and often captures the actions of
nominally private actors. States can violate the prohibition against torture
when, for example, “detention centers are privately owned or run . . . [such]
that personnel are acting in an official capacity on account of their
responsibility for carrying out the State function . . . to prevent torture and
ill-treatment.” CAT Committee GC 2. States can also violate the prohibition
against torture if “they fail to exercise due diligence,” to investigate and
intervene in potential torture or ill-treatment. Id. The prohibition also applies
to non-state actors who “exercise certain prerogatives that are comparable to
those normally exercised by legitimate governments.” Elmi v Australia (CAT,
1999). To date, neither the CAT Committee, ECtHR, HRC, nor any other relevant interpretative
body has distinguished ill-treatment as an obligation that might apply to
private actors more broadly than the prohibition on torture already might. Such
a distinction would, most likely, sit uncomfortably in a state-centric human
rights regime.
Often, legal distinctions, especially those of closely related concepts
like torture and ill-treatment, are made to delineate differential repercussions.
For example, those convicted of 1st degree homicide, 2nd
degree homicide or manslaughter receive different sentences. However,
international human rights does not distinguish ill-treatment from torture for any
such differentiated punitive application. At most, states that commit torture
are subject to more international condemnation, since the word torture carries
more stigma than ill-treatment. It is unlikely that any rigorous sanctions
follow findings that a state committed torture rather than ill-treatment. The
lack of penal differentiation is a feature of international human rights, which
is characterized by systems that are geared to enhance transparency but that are
backed by weak enforcement powers.
So, if international human rights does not distinguish between torture
and ill-treatment to tailor punishment to the crime, why does international
human rights distinguish between the two concepts?
One explanation might be the desire of states to retain policy flexibility
in their use of force. While torture is non-derogable (states may not, for any
reason, exempt themselves from the obligation not to torture), ill-treatment
might be. Torture is explicitly non-derogable in several treaties. CAT Art.
2(2), ECtHR Art. 15(2), ICCPR Art. 4(2). In contrast, there is no such
restriction on ill-treatment. The CAT said in its 2nd General
Comment that ill-treatment should also be non-derogable, but its wording is
telling: ill-treatment should be
non-derogable. States wrote and ratified the treaties, and they did not include
express provisions of non-derogability for ill-treatment. This can be read as a
sign that they wished to retain flexibility for coercive force that should not
be stigmatized as torture.
Another explanation is that the UDHR (and other relevant treaties)
introduced a broad prohibition that actually does not merit the distinctions
previously discussed. The UDHR prohibits ill-treatment just as forcefully as
torture. In practice, the definitional threshold between ill-treatment and
torture is often not clear because the conditions that give rise to
ill-treatment frequently facilitate torture. If ill-treatment is a precursor
to, or a less severe form of, torture, and there are no differences in
derogability or punishment, then there is no need to distinguish the two
concepts. Once state action meets the threshold for ill-treatment, that state
may be condemned. On this reading, international human rights distinguishes
between ill-treatment and torture either because of some misunderstandings
about why we make legal distinctions and operationalize treaty language, or
because there is value in distinguishing torture, because it does carry more
stigma, even though there are no hard legal repercussions as in criminal law.
Neither of these explanations is satisfactory. In fact, the differences
between ill-treatment and torture are muddled in the case law, as some
fact-specific assessment of severity and purpose, precisely because the legal
establishment does not have a coherent working thesis for why ill-treatment and
torture should be distinguished. To create useful rules or standards
distinguishing the two concepts, their purposes must be clarified.
The purpose of condemning states that commit torture should be to call
the attention of outside actors: states, companies and civil society, that a
particular geographic governance institution is corrupt in the most base, moral
sense. Torture should be used as a mechanism to highlight the worst coercive state
institutions in the world. Therefore, torture should be a prohibition on specific
state action. This is, essentially, the definition of torture today: incorporating
private actors who assume state functions and condemning non-action by states
that should investigate private acts. Findings of torture do carry substantial
stigma, which operates effectively against states, and keeping the definition
of torture relatively static comports with state obligations under relevant
treaties.
Ill-treatment, on the other hand, should be broadened a great deal. It
should serve a radically different purpose than torture; in fact, it should be
an altogether different concept. It can encompass lower thresholds of suffering,
although setting the threshold of suffering is a hard-to-define and
inconclusive exercise. As different and unrelated concepts, torture and
ill-treatment might encompass overlapping minimum thresholds of suffering, but
need not. More concretely, ill-treatment can be defined without reference to
purpose, intention, or to any particular actors, official or otherwise.
Ill-treatment should be used to highlight situations of broad social suffering,
to raise awareness of a systemic failure causing extreme suffering. While the
purpose of the prohibition on torture is to shame and isolate particular institutions,
the purpose of the prohibition on ill-treatment would be to galvanize action to
support and strengthen local governance and economic institutions to alleviate the
situation.
What are the legal repercussions of such a re-imagining of ill-treatment vis-à-vis
torture? Most radically, the requirement of state action or inaction melts away
in an analysis of ill-treatment. This change does not mean, however, that
ill-treatment operates against private actors. It simply means that proving the
existence of ill-treatment in a particular state does not require the
participation of anyone in particular. It may encompass a broad range of
actors. Otherwise, ill-treatment can still be assessed and brought-to-light
within the same human rights treaties and institutions that already exist.
Moreover, the CAT was correct to write that ill-treatment should also be
non-derogable. Some states may not derogate from what amounts to a prohibition
on systemic deprivation because (1) the deprivation is outside of their control
and (2) the motives of human rights institutions are to galvanize support for
the state to rectify the situation, or (3) because a state has the power to
create and maintain systemic deprivation and there are no good reasons why that
state should be allowed to exercise that power.
Comments
Post a Comment